![]() |
||||
THE HANDSTAND | january 2005 |
|||
Agamben's
Messianic Politics: Biopolitics, Abandonment and Happy
Life Excerpts
from her Essay in : My concern in this paper is to consider issues of life and death as political issues,to locate a .bio-politics., a politics of life, and a .thanato-politics., a politics of death, within our ways of thinking about and imagining politics. I follow two recent theorists, Michel Foucault and Giorgio Agamben, who are convinced that not only must we consider how we exercise powers of life and death in modern politics but how the very notion of politics and political community are intimately related to such issues. At issue is the power we call sovereign power, and its relation to this politics of life and death. I shall in turn consider four possible theses that can be derived from the work of these thinkers and from other twentieth century critical and legal theorists. Human life is politicized only through an abandonment to an unconditional power of death.1 In Homo Sacer, Agamben concludes the text
with an elusive gesture toward a new .form-of-life. as
the ground of a coming politics over and against the
bloody nexus of sovereign violence and biopolitics. The
key parable of Kafka for Agamben is "Before
the Law," in which a man from
the countrypresents himself before the doorkeeper who
refuses to let him enter through the door (of the law). Drawing
simultaneously on Aristotle, Carl Schmitt and Walter
Benjamin as well as the
Importantly, the theoretical point of inspiration for this claim comes from the eighth fragment of Benjamin.s "Theses on the Philosophy of History," where he writes that: The tradition of the oppressed teaches us that the "state of emergency" in which we live is not the exception but the rule. We must attain to a conception of history that is in keeping with this insight. Then we shall clearly realize that it is our task to bring about a real state of emergency, and will improve our position in the struggle against Fascism.27 Taking up the first theoretical provocation in this thesis, Agamben generalizes the sovereign exception such that it no longer appears as the exceptional case, but as the norm. This means that the capture of bare life within the exception is a general condition of existence, such that the rule and the exception, inclusion and exclusion, and right and violence are no longer clearly distinguishable. Agamben claims from this that under a regime of biopolitics all subjects are potentially homo sacers. That is, all subjects are at least potentially if not actually abandoned by the law and exposed to violence as a constitutive condition of political existence.28
As empirical evidence of this politicophilosophical claim, he cites the figure of homo sacer, genocidal violence, the apparently ever-expanding phenomenon of concentration campswhich he argues reveal the .nomos of the modern.as well as the redefinition of life and death in the categories of the .overcomatose. or brain dead, and neo-morts. Agamben has been heavily criticized for his apparently eclectic collection of empirical evidence and the rendering of these examples as .indistinguishable.. Yet, what unites the examples Agamben selects is the thesis on the generalization of the exception and the correlative indistinction of fact and norm in Western politics and philosophy. Even
so, one should not conclude from the rejection of
Foucault's more historically and empirically restrained
theses on the emergence and institutionalization of
biopower that Agamben sees no substantive difference
between classical and modern democracy. Rather, Agamben
suggests that what distinguishes modern democracy from
classical democracy is that the former "presents
itself from the beginning as a vindication and liberation
of zoe, and that it is constantly
trying to transform its own bare life into a way of life
and to find, so to speak, the bios of zoe."29 This
account of the aporetic violence of modern democracy
provides the starting point for the particular
formulation of political futurity that Agamben develops.
For according to Agamben, this aporia stymies any attempt
to oppose biopolitical regimes from within the framework
of bios and zoe. Such projects will tirelessly repeat
the aporia of the exception, the danger of which lies in
the gradual convergence of democracy with
totalitarianism. In other words, the condition of
abandonment indicates a fundamental aporia for
contemporary politics, where attempts to overcome the
capture of life within the sovereign exception through
recourse to natural life necessarily repeat and reinstall
that capture in their politicization of natural life. The
reference in this passage to the .beautiful day. of life
not only gestures toward the distinction Aristotle makes
between the great difficulty of bios and the natural sweetness of zoe, but offers the key to the
foundation of the coming politics that Agamben proposes.
I have
argued that Agamben's diagnosis of contemporary politics
as a condition in which the exception has become the rule
draws on Benjamin.s formulation in his "Theses on
the Philosophy of History." It is also important to
note the second part of this formulation here though, in
which Benjamin calls for the inauguration of a real state
of exception as a means of forestalling Fascism. Analogously, for Agamben, the overcoming of the sovereign ban that characterizes modern politics can only take place through the inauguration of a .form-of-life, or, happy life. that supersedes the distinction between bios and zoe. As he states in Means Without End: The "happy life" on which political philosophy should be founded thus cannot be either the naked life that sovereignty posits as a presupposition so as to turn it into its own subject or the impenetrable extraneity of science and of modern biopolitics that everybody tries in vain to sacralize. This "happy life" should be rather, an absolutely profane "sufficient life" that has reached the perfection of its own power and its own communicabilitya life over which sovereignty and right no longer have any hold.35 Thus, Agamben points toward a new conception of life, described as .happy life. or a .form-of-life., in which it is never possible to isolate bare life as the biopolitical subject. The happy life will be such that no separation between bios and zoe is possible, and life will find its unity in a pure immanence to itself, in .the perfection of its own power.. In this then, he seeks a politico-philosophical redefinition of life no longer founded upon the bloody separation of the natural life of the species and political life, but which is beyond every form of relation insofar as happy life is life lived in pure immanence, grounded on itself alone. While
Agamben's starting point for the theorization of bare
life is the term .mere life. that Benjamin uses in "Critique
of Violence," the inspiration for his
conception of a .happy life. derives at least in part
from the short text, "Theologico-Political
Fragment." In this, Benjamin explicitly
addresses the relation of Messianic and historic time and
writes that "only the Messiah himself consummates
all history, in the sense that he alone redeems,
completes, creates its relation to the Messianic."36Benjamin,
"Theologico-Political Fragment" 312). Constructing an image of two arrows
pointing in different directions but which are
nevertheless reinforcing, Benjamin goes on to say that
.the order of the profane should be erected on the idea
of happiness.. This is because while the profane cannot
in itself establish a relation with the Messianic, it
assists the coming of the Messianic Kingdom precisely by
being profane. In other words, while the profane is not a
category of the Messianic, it is "the decisive
category of its quietest approach," because
"the rhythm of Messianic nature is happiness."37 Agamben.s absolutely profane happy life draws on this characterization of the profane and Messianic, wherein the profane happy life provides passage for Messianic redemption. The
inauguration of happy life in which neither zoe nor bios can be isolated allows for the law in
force without significance to be overturned such that the
Nothing maintained by that law is eliminated and humanity
reaches its own fulfillment in its transparency to
itself. For Agamben, happy life might be characterized as
life lived in the experience of its own unity, its own
potentiality of "being-thus," and as such, is life lived beyond the reach of the law.40(Agamben, Means Without End 114-115) In his way, Agamben offers a redemptive hope that is external to the problems of biopolitics; the problems posed by the state of exception and sovereignty's capture of bare life are resolved by the inauguration of the happy life, and the coming politics it grounds redeem humanity in the face of biopolitical annihilation. To
summarize so far then, Agamben argues that bare life is
produced as the excrescence of the distinction between bios and zoe and as such, is the carrier of the
sovereign nexus of right and violence and the locus of
biopolitical capture. Against this situation, he points
toward a new conception of life, described as .happy
life. or a 'form-of-life', in which it is never possible
to isolate bare life as the biopolitical subject.41 The happy life will be such that no
separation of bios
and zoe is possible, and life will
find its unity in a pure immanence to itself, in .the
perfection of its own power.. Happy Life and the Force of Law: Agamben and Derrida As
provocative as it is, Agamben's gesture toward a happy
life that provides foundation for the coming politics
clearly warrants further consideration and to do this, I
turn to discussing the theoretical commitments that
underpin Agamben's theorization of biopolitics and the
sovereign exception. In particular, I consider the
messianic dimension of Agamben's theorization, which
derives from his theoretical debt to Walter Benjamin and
which is perceived to provide the means of overcoming the
structure of the ban idenitified in and through Schmitt.s
conception of sovereignty. The
notion of abandonment provides the point of departure for
this discussion, for it can now be said that for Agamben,
recognition of the status of law as being in force
without significance in the ban is insufficient as the
aim and achievement of contemporary thought, since
residing in this recognition does little other than
repeat the ontological structure of the sovereign ban.
Instead, Agamben claims that contemporary thought must
think abandonment beyond any conception of the law in
order to move toward a politics freed of every ban. The relation of abandonment is now to be thought in a new way. To read this relation as a being in force without significance that is, as Being's abandonment to and by a law that prescribes nothing, and not even itself is to remain inside nihilism and not to push the experience of abandonment to the extreme. Only where the experience of abandonment is freed from every idea of the law and destiny is abandonment truly experienced as such.43 This
complicated suggestion brings to light several crucial
aspects of Agamben's theorization of abandonment. First
and most obviously, this statement summarizes Agamben.s
critique of the conception of abandonment given by
Jean-Luc Nancy in his essay "Abandoned Being."
Nancy argues that abandonment is the conditionperhaps
the sole conditionof the thinking of being in the
contemporary world and, further, abandonment is always to
be abandoned in relation to law, since "abandonment
respects the law; it cannot do otherwise."44 He concludes that "abandonment's
only law
is to be without return and without
recourse."45
In
fact, this reference to nihilism is key for disentangling
Agamben.s commitment to a Benjaminian messianics as the
path of overcoming the condition of abandonment, for it
prefigures the distinction between perfect and imperfect
nihilism that he poses as synonymous with the virtual and
real state of exception posed by Benjamin in the "Theses
on the Philosophy of History." Benjamin's
fragment, cited above posits the generalization of the
state of exception and the correlative necessity of
developing an account of historical time that can clearly
illuminate and assist in realizing a means of overcoming
that state through the creation of a real state of
exception. The distinction that Benjamin posits between
the virtual and the real state of exception or state of
emergency can be understood as strictly analogous to a
differentiation between the state of exception that
constitutes sovereignty according to Schmitt.s thesis and
the exceptionality of the messianic, which redeems and
rescues humanity from the grip of the former. Given that the fragment from the "Theses on the Philosophy of History" presents a barely disguised critique of Schmitt,47 it provides Agamben with the solution to the perceived urgency of overcoming or escaping the operations of the sovereign ban and the biopolitical capture of bare life that this entails. Accepting the essential correlation between nihilism and messianism posited by Scholem and Benjamin, Agamben claims that it is necessary to distinguish between two forms of messianism or nihilism.48(Agamben, "The Messiah and the Sovereign" 171. The distinction Agamben poses between imperfect and perfect nihilism is similar to that between passive and active nihilism distinguished by Nietzsche in for instance Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, ed., trans. Walter Kaufman and R.J. Hollingdale (New York: Vintage, 1967), esp. 5-82 at 17. Additionally, one should see Heidegger.s discussion of nihilism in Martin Heidegger, "On the Question of Being" [1 55], Pathmarks, ed., trans. William McNeill (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1998) 291-322 and Mark Warren, Nietzsche and Political Thought (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1988).) The
first form, which he calls .imperfect nihilism. nullifies
the law but maintains "the Nothing [that is, the
emptiness of the law] in a perpetual and infinitely
deferred state of validity." This is the nihilism
that Agamben refers to above in his critique of Nancy.s
conception of abandonment. The second form, called
.perfect nihilism. overturns the Nothing, and does not
even permit the survival of validity beyond meaning;
perfect nihilism, as Benjamin states, "succeeds in
finding redemption in the overturning of the
Nothing."49
Importantly though, the overturning of the law does simply mean instituting a new law, and nor does it mean reinstating the lost law of a previous time "to recuperate alternative heredities."51 Both of these modes of progression would merely repeat the political aporia of abandonment. Rather, the task of redeeming life from the aporia of law in force without significance requires both the destruction of the past and the realization of "that which has never been."52 It is only the inauguration of that which has never been, the not having been of the past, that will suffice to overturn the Nothing maintained by the law in force without significance and thereby restore human life to the unity of bios and zoe, a unity that itself has never yet been. As Agamben states "thiswhat has never happenedis the historical and wholly actual homeland of humanity."53 In this
light, it becomes clear that the .form-of-life. or .happy
life. that Agamben proposes as the foundation of the
coming politics constitutes the .real state of exception.
from which the biopolitics of modern democracy and its
correlation with totalitarianism can be combated and life
redeemed. In this, the notion of happy life is structurally similar to the theoretical gesture that Agamben makes in his earlier text, The Coming Community. Though not formulated in the terms of bare and happy life, the messianic overturning of expropriated being provides the logical impetus of this text, in which Agamben develops his conception of community without essence realized in the .whatever. singularity. In this text, the community of whatever, the being-thus of humanity, which is neither general nor particular, without attribute or identity, is essentially a messianic community of humanity restored to its own potentiality, its own .being-in language. that thereby overturns being's expropriation by the Nothing of the spectacle to which it is currently condemned.55( Guy Debord.s classic analysis of the spectacle of commodification in The Society of the Spectacle, trans. D. Nicholson-Smith (New York: Zone Books, 1994), is crucial for Agamben.s political theory. However, to be clear this does not amount to a nostalgic re-invocation of Gemienschaft; rather, as should be expected from the structure of messianics, the coming community has never yet been. As Thomas Carl Wall comments, "without destiny and without essence, the community that returns is one never present in the first place."56(This also indicates and helps explain Agamben.s unequivocal insistence on the elimination of the dogma of the sacredness of life, for here he states that "a fulfilled foundation of humanity in itself necessarily implies the definitive elimination of the sacrificial mythologeme." (Agamben, "*Se" 137) This suggests that the gesture toward the necessity of a new form of life or happy life to ground the coming politics that appears in the final pages of Homo Sacer brings to light the formulation of messianism that underpins Agamben.s conceptions of life, politics and historical transformation developed in much of his recent work. Also Mitchell Dean :Four Theses on Life and Death My concern in this paper is to consider issues of life and death as political issues, to locate a .bio-politics., a politics of life, and a .thanato-politics., a politics of death, within our ways of thinking about and imagining politics. I follow two recent theorists, Michel
Foucault and Giorgio Agamben, who are convinced that not
only must we Friendship
- Giorgio Agamben and other texts.
Quoted by a friend, Bill Conroy, of Gary Webb, investigative journalist, recently dead of two gun-shot wounds to the head... that are described as suicide by the USA authorities.Rense.com
|